You can not select more than 25 topics Topics must start with a letter or number, can include dashes ('-') and can be up to 35 characters long.
Obsidian/00.03 News/Why it can be sublime to lo...

64 lines
10 KiB

This file contains ambiguous Unicode characters!

This file contains ambiguous Unicode characters that may be confused with others in your current locale. If your use case is intentional and legitimate, you can safely ignore this warning. Use the Escape button to highlight these characters.

---
Alias: [""]
Tag: ["Human", "Love"]
Date: 2022-02-15
DocType: "WebClipping"
Hierarchy:
TimeStamp:
Link: https://psyche.co/ideas/why-it-can-be-sublime-to-love-someone-who-doesnt-love-you-back?ref=refind
location:
CollapseMetaTable: true
---
Parent:: [[@News|News]]
Read:: [[2022-03-20]]
---
 
```button
name Save
type command
action Save current file
id Save
```
^button-WhyitcanbesublimetolovesomeonewhodoesntloveyoubackNSave
 
# Why it can be sublime to love someone who doesnt love you back
**If you have ever loved unrequitedly,** then you know that living without any hope for a future with your beloved is a bitter experience indeed. When in love, we usually have a deep desire that our beloved love us back. If they dont, it can pain us very much. We might, in all likelihood, come to wish that we didnt love them, that we could stop loving them, or even that we had never loved them at all. Even if you havent experienced this for yourself, then you can probably imagine the agony involved.
No wonder that people employ all kinds of techniques to get over those who dont come to love them back. In George Eliots novel _Daniel Deronda_ (1876), Rex Gascoigne, after being rebuffed by the dynamic Gwendolen Harleth, begs his father to allow him to defect from England to Canada. I too once toyed with the idea of fleeing to the Canadian Rockies in the wake of heartbreak in Toronto. Others might seek comfort in a weekend, or a few, of heavy drinking, or find themselves set up on a series of uncomfortable blind dates by overbearing sympathisers. Indeed, friends will offer us all sorts of concoctions and home remedies. Those who have loved unrequitedly, however, know: though this friendly advice is no doubt well meant, it is also misguided. For while the proposed remedies might give us time and opportunity to heal from the hurt of the disillusionment, they will not cause us to stop loving.
Why not? Because the fact that it would be better to stop loving is not itself sufficient to stop us loving. Prudential reasons to fall out of love simply miss the mark, given the nature and structure of love as _arational_. But the situation is not entirely wretched. I hope to persuade you that, while unrequited love is bitter, it can be made bittersweet, if you change your attitude toward it.
_Rational_ love is love justified by reasons: for example, we might imagine Leo Tolstoys character Anna Karenina loving Count Vronsky for the reasons that he is charming, persistent and attentive. Arational love, by contrast, is love that is [not justified](https://aeon.co/essays/russia-against-the-western-way-of-love) by such rationales. There are many reasons why I believe romantic love has this arational form, one of which is a puzzle known to philosophers of love as the problem of particularity. It goes like this: if its true that love is rational, and that we love people for reasons such as their charm, persistence and attentiveness, its not clear why we should love any one particular charming person over any other. All sorts of people are charming, persistent and attentive. Why love Vronsky?
If you are one of those who has loved unrequitedly, fear not, for there are compelling reasons to embrace your predicament
Some commentators, such as the philosopher Niko Kolodny, [believe](https://www.mit.edu/~shaslang/mprg/KolodnyLVR.pdf) it is the [shared](https://aeon.co/essays/simone-de-beauvoirs-authentic-love-is-a-project-of-equals) history of a relationship that solves the problem of particularity and provides a rational reason for romantic love. After all, while there might be many charming people in the world, only Count Vronsky first met Anna at that Moscow train station. In the case of unrequited love, however, there is a strong reason to doubt that this is correct. After all, doesnt unrequited love sometimes blossom upon first sight or develop over time for a near stranger? If love is possible in the absence of a relationship, the relationship cannot serve as its reason.
So I say that love is arational. In consequence, though it may indeed be better in a pragmatic sense for the heartbroken lover to move on, this higher-order reason will not cause or persuade us to actually move on. Love is not the sort of thing justified or undone by reasons.
Some might say, but what if this love is causing harm? If loving pains the unrequited lover, surely this, if nothing else, gives them reason to stop loving. Yet, I repeat once more, love is not the kind of thing that is swayed by reasons, even this one. To borrow from William Shakespeare, once in love, we can love someone even to the edge of doom. Take Charles Dickenss character Sydney Carton and his love for Lucie Manette in _A Tale of Two Cities_ (1859): though she did not love him but loved another still, he died for her sake, taking the place at the guillotine of the man whom she did love. In this way, we might even think of romantic love as not only arational, but also _unconditional_.
If you are one of those who has loved unrequitedly and you are persuaded by my arguments that your love is arational and unconditional, and therefore immune to rational or deliberate undoing, you might at this point be in some renewed distress. But please fear not, for I believe there are compelling reasons to embrace your predicament. (Note, I am not referring here to abusive relationships in which one partner withholds love as a means of manipulation.) I have already said that unrequited love can be deeply painful, and I stand by this but I hope you will forgive my saying that, if it is torture, it is torture of the most sublime and exquisite kind. And I believe that an exquisite torture is a torture worth bearing. The unrequited lover need not wish so impatiently for their love to end. Instead, they might embrace their love, for however long it persists. If you embrace your love, unrequited though it may be, it need not hurt you so.
**What does it mean to embrace love?** Well, though love itself is arational, it seems plausible that we can still take certain attitudes toward it, doing so for reasons. If we reject our love, this can cause in us a kind of rift we do not endorse our love, and yet we cant help but love. This results in a kind of alienation contributing to our ultimate experience of bitterness. If instead, however, you can adopt an attitude of affirmation, you need not be at odds with yourself. This is what I mean by embracing unrequited love: adopt an attitude of affirmation toward it by telling yourself: Im in love, and thats OK.
You might [worry](https://philpapers.org/archive/HIETWK.pdf) that prudential reasons for embracing your unrequited love are the wrong kinds of reasons; that the notion It would be better for me to embrace my love does not give you the right kind of reason to actually do so. Understandably, you might think that having certain attitudes requires having certain beliefs. For instance, that having an attitude of affirmation toward your love is not possible if you dont really believe that it is OK that you are in love. Fortunately, I can offer a powerful nonprudential reason for you to embrace your unrequited love: it is _sublime_.
Love is not a choice, and yet it is still something you do, not something which merely happens to you
That love is arational, and that we are capable of it, is something to rejoice in. Small, trembling creatures though we may be, we are capable of arational, unconditional love, which is the closest we may ever come to the infinite or the eternal. I am thinking of something akin to Immanuel Kants mathematical sublime, though I may be one of the only philosophers to accuse his third _Critique_ (1790) of being romantic. To paraphrase Kant, the fact that we are capable, over and above reason, of feeling something so immense, so overwhelmingly powerful, so beyond our control indicates a faculty … which surpasses every standard of sense.
To love is to exhibit a capacity beyond the capacity of sense, and even beyond that of reason. The depth of feeling of which we are capable is the ultimate expression of our humanity, and our relative helplessness before it is perhaps the essence of what makes us human. As W H Auden wrote: If equal affection cannot be, / Let the more loving one be me. If love is mathematically sublime, however, then it is only metaphorically so; surely love neednt be strictly either mathematical or dynamic in order to be sublime. After all, the [sublime](https://psyche.co/ideas/is-the-sublime-a-hopelessly-old-fashioned-euro-romantic-ideal) is, for Kant, the closest that one may ever get to peering over the edge, to looking beyond the phenomenal (thinkable) world.
Love is, therefore, perhaps best thought of as sublime because it either is, or at least gestures at, something that we cannot quite make sense of. Indeed, see how we look for the reasons of love we _want_ love to be rational so that it may be sensible! Yet love defies your sense-making strategies: love is not a choice, and yet it is still something you do, not something which merely happens to you. There is something incomprehensible about this, and this reflects a deep incomprehensibility and essential mystery about the nature of agency, even of our own agency over ourselves. Our experience of and attempts to analyse love are perhaps the closest we can come to having an account of the self that is outside of the limits of practical reason. Love is something that exists on the maximal outer limit of our agencys thinkability. Love is therefore sublime in that it gives us a glimpse of the supersensible.
In short, love including unrequited love is exceptional. It can endure anger, pain and grief, persisting against all odds, existing in the unlikeliest of places and times. Though it may pain you that your beloved does not love you back, take comfort in loving, you are peering over Kants edge. The edge is not something to be shied away from, though it is formidable. Rather, regard the precipice with [awe](https://psyche.co/guides/how-to-fill-your-life-with-more-awe-every-single-day) and rejoice in your proximity. Though this claim may not be ultimately satisfactory to some, I mean it to be more than a salve. Romantic or otherwise, returned or not, love is sublime and worthy of embrace because it reveals in you, the lover, a unique and noble capacity.